Comments

I didn't log the time I spent on the original blog post, and it's kinda hard to assign hours to this since most of the reading and thinking for the post happened while working on the modeling aspects of the MTAIR project. If I count just the time I sat down to write the blog post, I would guess maybe less than 20 hours.

As for the "convert the post to paper" part, I did log that time and it came out to 89 hours, so David's estimate of "perhaps another 100 hours" is fairly accurate.

Did you end up running it through your internal infohazard review and if so what was the result?

Rob, are you able to disclose why people at Open Phil are interested in learning more decision theory? It seems a little far away from the AI strategy reports they've been publishing in recent years, and it also seemed like they were happy to keep funding MIRI (via their Committee for Effective Altruism Support) despite disagreements about the value of HRAD research, so the sudden interest in decision theory is intriguing.

I was reading parts of Superintelligence recently for something unrelated and noticed that Bostrom makes many of the same points as this post:

If the frontrunner is an AI system, it could have attributes that make it easier for it to expand its capabilities while reducing the rate of diffusion. In human-run organizations, economies of scale are counteracted by bureaucratic inefficiencies and agency problems, including difficulties in keeping trade secrets. These problems would presumably limit the growth of a machine intelligence project so long as it is operated by humans. An AI system, however, might avoid some of these scale diseconomies, since the AI’s modules (in contrast to human workers) need not have individual preferences that diverge from those of the system as a whole. Thus, the AI system could avoid a sizeable chunk of the inefficiencies arising from agency problems in human enterprises. The same advantage—having perfectly loyal parts—would also make it easier for an AI system to pursue long-range clandestine goals. An AI would have no disgruntled employees ready to be poached by competitors or bribed into becoming informants.

So the existence of this interface implies that A is “weaker” in a sense than A’.

Should that say B instead of A', or have I misunderstood? (I haven't read most of the sequence.)

Does anyone know how Brian Christian came to be interested in AI alignment and why he decided to write this book instead of a book about a different topic? (I haven't read the book and looked at the Amazon preview but couldn't find the answer there.)

HCH is the result of a potentially infinite exponential process (see figure 1) and thereby, computationally intractable. In reality, we can not break down any task into its smallest parts and solve these subtasks one after another because that would take too much computation. This is why we need to iterate distillation and amplification and cannot just amplify.

In general your post talks about amplification (and HCH) as increasing the capability of the system and distillation as saving on computation/making things more efficient. But my understanding, based on this conversation with Rohin Shah, is that amplification is also intended to save on computation (otherwise we could just try to imitate humans). In other words, the distillation procedure is able to learn more quickly by training on data provided by the amplified system compared to just training on the unamplified system. So I don't like the phrasing that distillation is the part that's there to save on computation, because both parts seem to be aimed at that.

(I am making this comment because I want to check my understand with you or make sure you understand this point because it doesn't seem to be stated in your post. It was one of the most confusing things about IDA to me and I'm still not sure I fully understand it.)

I still don't understand how corrigibility and intent alignment are different. If neither implies the other (as Paul says in his comment starting with "I don't really think this is true"), then there must be examples of AI systems that have one property but not the other. What would a corrigible but not-intent-aligned AI system look like?

I also had the thought that the implicative structure (between corrigibility and intent alignment) seems to depend on how the AI is used, i.e. on the particulars of the user/overseer. For example if you have an intent-aligned AI and the user is careful about not deploying the AI in scenarios that would leave them disempowered, then that seems like a corrigible AI. So for this particular user, it seems like intent alignment implies corrigibility. Is that right?

The implicative structure might also be different depending on the capability of the AI, e.g. a dumb AI might have corrigibility and intent alignment equivalent, but the two concepts might come apart for more capable AI.

IDA tries to prevent catastrophic outcomes by searching for a competitive AI that never intentionally optimises for something harmful to us and that we can still correct once it’s running.

I don't see how the "we can still correct once it’s running" part can be true given this footnote:

However, I think at some point we will probably have the AI system autonomously execute the distillation and amplification steps or otherwise get outcompeted. And even before that point we might find some other way to train the AI in breaking down tasks that doesn’t involve human interaction.

After a certain point it seems like the thing that is overseeing the AI system is another AI system and saying that "we" can correct the first AI system seems like a confusing way to phrase this situation. Do you think I've understood this correctly / what do you think?

Load More